.

On the Road Again

Reviewed by Yehoshua Porath

The Road to Serfdom
by Friedrich Hayek
200 pages, Hebrew.



Few in Israel are familiar with the writings of Friedrich Hayek, the Viennese economist whose critique of modern socialism laid the groundwork for the dramatic reemergence of classical liberalism over the past two decades. Yet Hayeks works, and in particular The Road to Serfdom, are of immediate relevance to Israel: As the country struggles to shed its Marxist economic heritage, a belief in government restraint and economic liberty has yet to take hold in an Israeli public that has long accepted confiscatory taxation, mammoth bureaucracy and rampant cronyism as a matter of course. Even if Hayek has been largely abused by Western conservatives (including The Road to Serfdoms Hebrew editor, Ofir Haivry) who have painted him as a defender of all things traditional, Hayeks Hebrew debut will serve as a beacon for revolutionaries in Israel – a country where centralized planning is the only economic tradition known, and a belief in the free market the emerging wave of the future.
 
Friedrich August von Hayek was born into a family of Austrian nobility, which in earlier times had served the Hapsburg dynasty. Raised in a scholarly environment, he became a serious student of law, political theory and economics. Economics eventually became his chief area of concentration, but his work in the field, including that on monetary theory, always was built upon philosophical-ethical foundations. In Great Britain, where in 1931 he assumed the post of economics professor at the London School of Economics, and in the United States, where he taught at the University of Chicago during the 1950s, Hayek expounded the principles that would be known as the Viennese school of economic thought, remaining ever faithful to eighteenth-century liberalism while developing its conceptual and analytical tools.
A tireless advocate of liberty, Hayek assailed the economic policies undertaken by Britain and other Western nations from the 1930s onward. The economic crisis which devastated capitalist economies around the world in 1929, coupled with the failure of liberal economists to find a cure for mass unemployment, had compelled Western governments to give the new theories of John Maynard Keynes a try. In sharp contrast to classical liberalism, Keynesian economics called upon government to “manage aggregate demand” by intervening massively in the economy. Hayek disagreed sharply with this idea; together with Arthur Cecil Pigou, the foremost liberal economist in Britain, Hayek argued that Keynes proposals would increase aggregate demand and production only in the short run: Beyond that, however, artificially inflating demand through deficit financing would necessarily lead to spiraling inflation.
The siege conditions of World War II dramatically accelerated the centralization of Britains economy, much as World War I had for that of Germany. Under the leadership of Winston Churchill, but with the active collaboration of the Labor Party, the British government directed the economy via administrative decrees, targeting production in support of the war effort; workers were assigned to vital industries, and consumers became accustomed to a limited selection of goods, sold at fixed prices. This policy entailed significant restrictions on personal liberty: Manufacturers could no longer decide what they would produce or at what price it would be sold, workers could not choose their places of employment, consumers could not choose how to spend their money. Yet out of concern for the war effort, the people of Britain accepted these policies, despite the infringement upon their basic freedoms.
The popularity of these policies during the war allowed Labor to call for continuing them after the wars end—a proposal which, in Hayeks view, would imperil liberty and economic efficiency if put into practice. He wrote The Road to Serfdom as the war was drawing to a close, in the hope of persuading the public to stay off the path of peacetime centralization, a path which, he maintained, could lead the country towards a totalitarianism not unlike what had gripped both Germany and Russia.
 
This objective set the tone for The Road to Serfdom, a sophisticated polemic which has been highly influential since it first appeared in 1944. It calls for a return to the basic idea of economic liberalism—a free and competitive market, with the government essentially relegated to the role of watchdog. The Road to Serfdom presents no real theoretical innovations, offering instead a reiteration of the liberal economic principles dating back to Adam Smith: That governments are incapable of planning production so that it will meet the varied demands of millions of people; that the state lacks adequate information regarding consumers wishes, information which the market alone supplies to manufacturers; that government is no substitute for the marketplaces thousands of manufacturers, who must constantly make decisions in real time; and so forth. In recent decades, these beliefs have become the consensus, earning the allegiance of even those who had been their sharpest critics. At least with respect to the productive sector of economic and social life, the principle of free-market policymaking is now almost universally accepted.
Yet The Road to Serfdom goes beyond economics. Its emphasis is on the moral and political ramifications of the planned economy. Hayek argues that the governments accretion of physical and fiscal power at the expense of the citizenry opens the door for threats to liberty, and not just economic liberty. He argues forcefully that in the absence of economic freedom, there is no future for political freedom or that at the very least, political freedom will be in constant jeopardy.
But like any good polemic, The Road to Serfdom underplays that which fails to support its case. In all likelihood, Keynesian theory would never have attained such wide acceptance were it not for the unprecedented financial crisis and massive unemployment of the 1930s. Yet the book contains not one reference to this, nor even to the larger historical context giving rise to the labor movement and socialism in Europe. The rapid industrialization in Great Britain, and soon experienced in other Western countries as well, spawned an ever-growing urban working class. Once the liberals had won the struggle for universal suffrage, it was a foregone conclusion that workers organized into trade unions would strive to translate their collective power into political strength by setting up political parties. These would always seek ways to improve the workers status and redress the unequal allocation of revenues. The result was a grassroots socialism that was neither totalitarian in spirit nor Leninist in its methods.
Yet in Hayeks view, all the “collectivists” were more or less identical: The communists, the social democrats, the fascists, the Nazis, and even Ferdinand Lassalle and Johann Fichte—anyone who ascribed any degree of importance to government action in the economic realm. To back up such a claim, Hayek was careful to remind us that many of the leaders and theoreticians of fascism were former socialists. And indeed, Mussolini was, as were Georges Sorel and Jacques Doriot. Even Werner Sombart, the famous German economist who supported state intervention in the economy in accordance with the teachings of Friedrich List, gradually changed his views and late in life began to favor Nazism.
Yet a much larger number of fascists and Nazis were never socialist activists. Among the leaders of Nazi Germany, few if any attained prominence as a Socialist or Communist Party activist before becoming active Nazis. Friedrich Naumann, who fathered the theory of “social imperialism” during the first two decades of the twentieth century, did combine German nationalism and imperialism with demands for social legislation. Yet he was no socialist, and if he was a ‘”former Marxist,” as Hayek dubs him, this was evidently in his youth, before he began formulating his theory and publishing his books. Even the socialist connection of Paul Lensch, who was a parliamentary delegate of Germanys Social Democrat Party, is tenuous. Before World War I he belonged to the left wing of the Social Democrats, yet once the war was under way he joined their right-wing nationalist branch and, ultimately, he left the party. In other words, in order to become a spokesman for German nationalism, he had to withdraw from the Socialist Party. Does he really demonstrate a necessary connection between democratic socialism and totalitarian collectivism?


From the
ARCHIVES

Operation Cast Lead and the Ethics of Just WarWas Israel's conduct in its campaign against Hamas morally justified?
Secret of the SabbathIt isn’t about R&R. It’s about how to be a creative human being.
Facts Underground 
Zohan and the Quest for Jewish UtopiaAdam Sandler's hit comedy reflects a deep divide between Israeli and American Jews.
Levi Eshkol, Forgotten HeroIsrael’s third prime minister offers a different model of Jewish leadership.

All Rights Reserved (c) Shalem Press 2025