The Supreme Court is a body of great power. Once on the court, a Justice wields that power without democratic check. This is as it should be. But is it not wise, before that power is put in his hands for life, that a nominee be screened by the democracy in the fullest possible manner...?
—Charles Lund Black1
It is an axiom of democratic theory that the judicial branch of government should not itself be “democratic.” Courts are not supposed to represent the popular sentiment of the day, but rather to serve as a bulwark against the excesses of majority rule. Yet there is something different about
For decades, the judicial selection process attracted little attention or criticism. The courts had to be protected, it was believed, against the pressures of a political culture not known for its deeply held democratic traditions. The rule of law, in the early decades of the state, needed all the help it could get, and the creation of an independent judiciary was given top priority. But since the current selection process for Supreme Court justices was introduced in 1953, the courts have grown much more powerful than they originally were. Executive actions have come under judicial review on a routine basis, often being reversed for reasons that are barely recognizable as having to do with law. In 1992, the Knesset handed the court the power to strike down legislation which does not conform with
Yet while its power has grown, the court has become, after decades of self-selection, distant from and unrepresentative of the citizenry. It is only natural that a group of expert justices, given the right to choose their own replacements, will prefer to appoint judges who are similar in outlook, temperament and background to themselves. As a result, the Israel Supreme Court is characterized today by a pronounced intellectual and professional homogeneity. Nearly all the justices are professional jurists, the products of
II
Every democracy that accords its judiciary a substantial role in constitutional affairs must find a way to balance two competing principles: Judicial independence, which demands that judges be protected from external pressures that may compromise the integrity of their rulings; and judicial accountability, which requires that judicial decisions respond to the fundamental, constitutive values of the nation whose laws they are interpreting.
Proper adjudication demands that judges be insulated from external pressures. Since judicial decisions frequently help or harm the fortunes of political actors—politicians, interest groups and so forth—it is imperative that judges never be dependent on their graces. Judges must also be free to act contrary to public opinion, since they alone can prevent majorities from violating individual or minority rights to achieve a popular aim. To ensure judicial independence, most democracies provide lifetime tenure and a guaranteed salary for the justices of their highest court; the idea being that judges who have reached the peak of professional accomplishment, and whose position and salary are guaranteed, will not easily be pressured into abandoning their role as defenders of law and justice.3
Yet “law” and “justice” are themselves problematic terms. Adjudication, and especially constitutional interpretation, is not merely a matter of combining technical proficiency with professional integrity. Rather, judges are constantly faced with the limitations of the written law, and are forced at every turn to apply their own conceptions and values in formulating their decisions. In the process, they often find themselves creating new legal categories—effectively writing the law with their own hand.
This fact, that judges often do not merely apply the law but actually create it, has been universally recognized by legal scholars throughout the world, including in
As makers of law, supreme courts inevitably make decisions on issues in which competing values—often the values which are most hotly disputed among the citizens—are pitted against one another. High court justices decide which values are to be expressed in the law, and these decisions are dependent in large part on their personal ideas of what is good for the country, rather than their professional analysis of legal texts. As Yale University legal scholar Charles L. Black noted, “it has been a very long time since anybody who thought about the subject to any effect has been possessed by the illusion that a judge’s judicial work is not influenced and formed by his whole lifeview, by his economic and political comprehensions, and by his sense, sharp or vague, of where justice lies in respect of the great question of his time.... It would be hard to find a well-regarded modern thinker who asserted the contrary.”7 Thus, legal scholars Jeffrey Segal and Harold Spaeth have shown that while the form of judicial decisions adheres closely to legal models, their content is better described in the context of overarching ideologies. In the American context, for example, “the Supreme Court decides disputes in light of the facts of the case vis-à-vis the ideological attitudes and values of the justices. Simply put, Rehnquist voted the way he did because he is extremely conservative;
The influence of the justices’ ideological outlook upon the law, then, is a pronounced one, and will be more pronounced to the degree that they are asked to rule on questions of a constitutional nature. Because such cases turn on abstract principles, they contain the greatest amount of ambiguity, and therefore demand the exercise of wide individual discretion in resolving them. At the same time, these cases also have the broadest impact, since they are essentially enshrining values into law. In addition, courts that are motivated by a philosophy of judicial activism, and therefore make decisions that could otherwise be left to the judgment of elected officials, further amplify the impact of the justices’ worldview upon the law of the land.
The composition of the highest court is therefore of paramount importance, since it determines whether the picture these “artists” are “creating” will reflect not only their own belief system, but also that of the nation which will have to live by their rulings. The question then becomes: How does a nation ensure that the small body entrusted with the task of constitutional judgment really reflects its basic values? How do we prevent the cloistered Supreme Court from becoming a judicial ivory tower, isolated from the public’s beliefs and aspirations, without opening it up to the direct pressure of public opinion? How, in short, can we create an accountable judiciary without compromising its independence?
III
The solution adopted by nearly all democratic nations is to give representative bodies the leading role in selecting highest-level judges, while ensuring that the latter are protected from external pressures once they are appointed. The original model for democratic judicial screening procedures is the one set forth in the
Under the American system, all appointees to the federal bench, including the Supreme Court, are nominated by the democratically elected president, and subject to confirmation by the Senate, whose members are chosen by popular votes within each state. The president’s nominee appears before the Senate to give testimony in a public hearing that is open-ended, and that affords senators a full opportunity to inquire into any aspects of the nominee’s qualifications, experience, judicial philosophy and ideological orientation that they deem relevant. The hearing consists of a freewheeling question-and-answer session, which may last for hours, days or weeks, followed by open debate among the senators, and finally the vote to confirm or reject the nomination. In the view of American constitutional scholar Herman Schwartz, the Senate confirmation proceeding obligates each senator to “ensure that a judicial nominee will further and not undermine the senator’s vision of the Constitution.... The nominee’s social, political, and judicial beliefs are all relevant….”12 The history of American judicial selection supports this contention: As Schwartz has noted, over the course of two hundred years, “one in five nominations” to the Supreme Court “has been rejected by the Senate, often for philosophical or political reasons; of some twenty-nine rejections or withdrawals under fire, almost a third were because of the nominee’s views on public issues.”13
The continual replacement of retiring Supreme Court justices with new ones who must clear a series of democratic hurdles has provided a natural corrective, steering the court over time in the same direction as the nation’s overarching values. For example, as a broad public consensus formed around the economic programs of Franklin Delano Roosevelt in the 1930s and 1940s, the President earned Senate approval for new Supreme Court nominees who shared the nation’s overwhelming support for New Deal policies. Likewise, as conservative family values made their comeback and the excesses of egalitarianism came to be understood in the 1980s and early 1990s, the Supreme Court nominations of that time shifted the balance on the court as well. Over the decades, the court has been involved in a number of highly controversial decisions, but has maintained the respect of the overwhelming majority of the American people nonetheless. One reason for its success has been that citizens who are unhappy with the decisions of a particular court understand that, in the long run, democratic means can bring about a change. The Supreme Court is insulated from day-to-day pressures, but the common man does not feel that he is helpless to shape its character in the long run.
The wisdom of the American system of judicial selection has convinced virtually every democratic country in the world to follow suit. While democracies vary greatly in their approaches to the role of the constitutional courts, and to the particular means for selecting court justices, what has united them is the belief that if the country’s highest court is to retain its attentiveness to the constitutive values of a living, evolving nation, the lead in selecting the justices of that court must be taken by the people’s elected representatives. In some cases, it is the legislature that chooses the justices of the top court. In
The same pattern repeats itself throughout the democratic world. In addition to the countries mentioned above, elected officials play the dominant role in appointing justices in the Czech Republic, Denmark, Greece, Hungary, Ireland, Italy, Macedonia, Poland, Portugal, Spain, Slovakia and Slovenia, as well as in the former-Soviet republics of Estonia, Latvia, Ukraine, Belarus and Russia. Outside of Europe and
Around the world, democracies have developed a variety of judicial selection processes, each according to the particularities of its traditions and constitutional makeup. What unites them all, however, is the basic commitment to a democratically accountable judiciary, and the understanding that even if the unique problems of justice mean that judges must be granted complete independence once in office, the constitutional court as a whole must be held accountable to the nation through a selection process dominated by the people’s elected representatives.
IV
In
Under the Basic Law: The Judiciary, all civil and criminal court judges, including Supreme Court justices, are appointed by a nine-member Judicial Selections Committee.17 The committee is made up of the president of the Supreme Court, two other Supreme Court justices chosen by the court, the justice minister, an additional minister appointed by the government, two Knesset members, and two representatives of the Israeli Bar Association. In other words, a majority of the Judicial Selections Committee’s members—the three justices and the two Bar representatives—are not chosen by the Israeli public, and are not accountable to it.
This mixture of representative and unrepresentative members results in a body whose decisions are completely unrepresentative of the public sentiment. This becomes clear when we examine the way competing interests are positioned on the committee. The four politicians all represent diffuse interests. By tradition, one of the Knesset members represents the government and the other the opposition, which means the two are more likely than not to disagree when matters of ideology are at stake. The justice minister is the single member of the government least appropriate for representing popular interests against the views of the justices, since he is usually a lawyer himself, advised by the judicial establishment and often beholden to it;18 he is therefore likely to disagree with the other government minister, whose principal loyalty is to the government and to the values of the electorate that put that government in power.19 The five representatives of the legal establishment, however, have their interests neatly lined up: The three justices will naturally become a single voting bloc, protecting the interests and prevailing views of the Supreme Court itself. Moreover, it is safe to assume that the selection of the two junior justices to the committee will have been heavily influenced, if not dictated, by the court president, himself a member of the committee. As for the representatives of the Bar Association, they are seen within their own fields as inferiors in the legal hierarchy, of which the judges are the apex, and it is they who will pay a price for failing to represent the very same values that the judges are defending.20
In practice, the three justices on the committee do vote as a bloc, and it is their vote which almost always determines the outcome. A good illustration of this point is the 1995 appointment of State Attorney Dorit Beinish to the Supreme Court. In 1993, her appointment was considered and rejected because she was regarded by the Supreme Court justices to be less qualified than the other candidates. The vote at the time was five to four against, with the five negative votes coming from the three justices, led by Supreme Court President Meir Shamgar, and the two Bar Association representatives. At the time, the daily newspaper Ha’aretz reported that the justices presented a united front despite “persistent rumors” of sharp differences of opinion among them.21 Two years later, her appointment was again considered, but by this time Shamgar had retired and been replaced by Aharon Barak, a longtime personal friend of Beinish. Even though her qualifications had not substantially changed (she was still State Attorney), the vote this time was nine to zero in favor of her nomination.22 Later, Barak himself admitted that it was he who had “initiated” Beinish’s appointment.23 Effectively, this meant that Barak’s appointment as Supreme Court President shifted five of the nine votes on the committee, and reversed the previous decision. The importance of this particular appointment should not be underestimated: By tradition, the presidency of the court—an office substantially more powerful than that of the chief justice of the United States Supreme Court24—is given to the justice who has served longest on the Supreme Court. When Barak retires at age seventy in the year 2006, Beinish will replace him as president. In other words, just two years after Beinish was rejected for a position on the court due to her lack of qualifications, Barak was able to hand-pick her as his successor.
Sometimes, of course, the forces do not line up as predicted; yet even then, the three-justice bloc almost always carries the day. A case in point is the appointment of
The influence of the justices is so evident that defenders of the system do not even bother to deny it; instead of conceding what amounts to a stunning affront to democratic principle, they seize upon it as a venerable tradition. Yitzhak Olshan, who was the Supreme Court’s president from 1953-1965, relates with pride that during his tenure, there was little dissent in the selection of justices. “Throughout the entire period, all the committee’s decisions were agreed upon almost unanimously. In most cases there was cooperation between the justices, the attorneys and the justice minister.”27 And Moshe Ben-Ze’ev, who served as attorney-general from 1963-1968, has observed that “it is hard to imagine the appointment of a judge, and certainly not of a Supreme Court justice, that contradicts the united opinion of the three Supreme Court justices on the committee. I hope that this is an unwritten rule—if not, I think it should be enshrined in law.”28
This remarkable statement can be fully understood only by taking a look at the way the current system came to be, and the degree to which the legal and judicial establishment has acted to protect this accumulation of power in its own hands. Under the Courts Ordinance in effect following the establishment of the State of Israel in 1948, justices were nominated by the justice minister, approved by the government and confirmed by the Knesset, a system similar to that which is practiced in most democratic countries.29 Attorney-General Elyakim Rubinstein has characterized the early system as “an appropriate arrangement which permitted the executive branch to appoint judges to the Supreme Court—but placed confirmation power in the hands of the legislative branch, similar to the American practice.”30 Yet these safeguards proved inadequate to instill a norm of democratic control over the judicial selection process. While the country’s institutions were in flux and the public’s attention was distracted from constitutional considerations, the legal establishment wasted no time in claiming for itself the right to absolute control over the selection process. The first justice minister, Pinhas Rosen, was able to recommend none other than his own law partner, Moshe Smoira, to be the first president of Israel’s Supreme Court in 1948.31 Throughout the spring and summer of 1948, Rosen and Smoira carried on an intense correspondence, hammering out an agreed list of candidates to fill the remaining seats on Israel’s first Supreme Court. During the first years of the state, all but one of the candidates on Smoira’s list became Supreme Court justices, including a number who were rejected when first nominated.32
Together with Rosen, the justices on the newly constituted Supreme Court embarked upon a broad campaign to eliminate legislative supervision of the judiciary. In 1951, Rosen introduced legislation, which he had prepared in consultation with the justices, that would effectively seal off the judiciary from the political system. “It is the lot of all enlightened peoples,” declaimed Rosen before the Knesset, “that every judge be independent and under no obligation to account for his decisions, except to his own conscience.”
Over the years, the Supreme Court has done everything in its power to protect or even augment its domination of the selection process. In 1978, Justice Meir Shamgar (later president of the court) called for the expansion of the committee’s judicial component for the sake of the appearance of judicial independence.36 More recently, Aharon Barak has waged a preemptive campaign to convince the public that nothing could be so disastrous as the introduction of democratic controls on the selection of justices. Speaking before members of the Knesset Constitution, Law and Justice Committee in October 1996, Barak voiced his opinion thus: “May God save you from any attempt to bring about a politicization of the structure and composition of the highest judicial body. God in heaven, you can’t have constitutional justice that way. It would be a tragedy for the country if appointments to the constitutional court were political….”37
In the effort to reach an ideal of perfect judicial independence—what Rubinstein has called a “hermetic seal” between the judiciary and elected officials—Israel has adopted a system in which the judiciary is accountable to no one, justices are appointed by a committee whose hearings are held in secrecy and dominated by the sitting justices, and the nation is left without any real say in the question of who will interpret its laws. The Israeli legal scholar Ze’ev Segal has pointed out that “the main aim of the system is to minimize possible political influence on the selection of judicial officers”—“political influence” meaning, among other things, “intervention in the process by … members of the legislative and the executive branches....”38 The Supreme Court, not surprisingly, is quite pleased with this system—former Supreme Court President Simon Agranat termed it “the best in the world”39—for the result is that the justices can, and do, shape the courts in their own image.
V
What happens when membership in an elite group of people is determined by the members themselves? Invariably, the result is a team of individuals whose ideas and thoughts bear a strong resemblance to one another. While Israel possesses one of the most diverse populations in the world—the vast majority of its citizens are either immigrants or the children of immigrants, representing a broad range of political and cultural traditions—its judicial selection process has produced a bland and intellectually uniform Supreme Court, leaving the opinions and concerns of a substantial majority of the Israeli public underrepresented, or not represented at all.
The problem is not, as is usually claimed, one of ethnic or religious homogeneity. Much has been made of the fact that the religious and ethnic makeup of the Supreme Court is overwhelmingly secular-Ashkenazi.40 But to dwell on the ethnic or religious makeup of the court is to miss the point: There is a more dangerous type of homogeneity, cultural and intellectual, which has come to characterize the courts in Israel, and increasingly so in recent years.
Consider, for example, the lack of professional diversity which has characterized the court since the current selection process was instituted in 1953. The eleven justices appointed from 1948 to 1953 included five judges, three private lawyers, one diplomat, one professor of Jewish literature and one ministry director-general. By contrast, the thirty-two justices appointed since 1954 include twenty-three lower court judges and five senior Justice Ministry lawyers (three attorney-generals and two state attorneys), two law professors, one professor of Jewish law and one private lawyer. This last, appointed in 1992, was the first privately practicing lawyer to be appointed since 1948.41
This professional homogeneity is accompanied by a uniformity in the educational background of the justices, a similarity which again has nothing to do with ethnic or religious background. Of the fifteen permanent and acting justices on the Supreme Court today, not one holds a degree in any field other than law.42 This is especially troubling in light of the narrowness of the education which Israeli law students receive: While in most Western countries a bachelor’s degree in the humanities includes exposure to a broad range of basic cultural and philosophical sources, in Israel this is not the case. Future attorneys and judges begin their academic studies already specializing in law, and often have little or no exposure to the most basic texts in other fields—even those fields that may bear directly upon the judgments which they will have to make. Areas such as political philosophy, economic theory, international relations, Jewish law, history, literature and the arts are, for many jurists, a closed book. As Rubinstein phrases it in his characteristic understatement, “the justices who have been appointed were not, generally, individuals known for their exposure to public and social affairs....”43
All this adds up to a narrowness of mind which is wholly incompatible with the task of constitutional adjudication. In order to determine the constitutionality of an action or law, judges must take into account the implications of the ruling in a wide variety of contexts. As the constitutional scholar Eugene Rostow has put it, “there is a political element in constitutional interpretation, requiring a judge to be thoroughly steeped in the history and public life of the country.”
The incompetence of the current Supreme Court to conduct constitutional judgment for the Jewish state has become increasingly evident in recent years, particularly since the 1992 passage of the Basic Law: Freedom of Occupation and the Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty. Both of these laws, which the courts have understood as having constitutional stature, guarantee the protection of basic human freedoms, which can only be abrogated by laws that are consistent with “the values of the State of Israel as a Jewish and democratic state.” These values remain unspecified, yet a simple reading of the text yields a limited range of reasonable interpretations for what those “Jewish and democratic” values could possibly be. Since the establishment of Israel, the idea of a “Jewish” state has found expression in a large number of laws, such as the Law of Return granting automatic citizenship to Jewish immigrants from around the world, provision for Jewish education within the general school system, and the granting of a special public status to particularistic institutions such as the Jewish Sabbath.
Instead of attempting to interpret the Israeli tradition of what a Jewish state is, the inclination of the
It is also troubling because these Basic Laws themselves are at the core of
A further example of the kinds of problems which arise from a homogeneous, insular court can be seen in Aharon Barak’s now-infamous “enlightened community” test.46 When, in 1994, Barak declared that contradictions between the democratic and Jewish values of the state should be resolved “according to the views of the enlightened community in Israel,”47 he did not seem to be aware of the term’s stunning antidemocratic implications—that the values of a particular community, rather than those of the country as a whole, should reign in the determination of law—nor of the impact of the expression on the public’s opinion of the court. Predictably, the term sparked a scandal. Columnist Ben-Dror Yemini accused the Barak Court of “circumventing democracy in favor of the ideological coterie that controls the court,”48 and former Supreme Court President Moshe Landau used the phrase “judicial fundamentalism” in describing Barak’s “enlightened community” test.49
But perhaps more importantly, the phrase was seized upon by those segments in the public who already felt alienated by the homogeneous court, and held up as proof of what they had long suspected: That the Israeli Supreme Court was an elitist, exclusive body advancing the interests of a particular group, rather than the ardent protector of liberty and justice for all. Since then, attacks on the court routinely make reference to the “enlightened community” test. While it is not clear precisely what Barak meant by the term (he has been difficult to pin down on the subject, and has distanced himself from the term in recent years), it does not really matter: It seems inconceivable that an idea so offensive to the public, so contemptuous of widely held values, so ignorant of the harm it would do to the court itself, could have been propagated and consistently reaffirmed by a court president who was not surrounded by colleagues more or less of the same mind.
Unfortunately, the court’s monolithic character and the growing gap between its values and those of the public are already beginning to take their toll on the court’s prestige. In a democracy, even a relatively young one such as
While the opinions of the court can help to shape our national understanding of ourselves, the roots of its decisions must already be in the nation. The aspirations voiced by the court must be those the community is willing not only to avow but in the end to live by. For the power of the great constitutional decisions rests upon the accuracy of the court’s perception of this kind of common will and upon the court’s ability, by expressing its perception, ultimately to command a consensus.50
Perhaps the gravest danger to the Israeli judiciary comes from the inability of many Israeli jurists to understand this simple fact. Instead, they have convinced themselves that the domination of the system by a handful of judges isolated from popular opinion somehow enhances the public confidence in the court. In the words of Ze’ev Segal, “The fact that the Selections Committee contains a significant plurality of jurists prevents, to a large extent, political abuse of the appointment process and ensures public confidence in the judiciary.”51 The shocking implications of Segal’s statement are that if the judiciary were selected by the democratically elected representatives of the Israeli people, the people would no longer have confidence in it; that the Israeli public is disinterested in exercising its sovereign prerogative of choosing those who govern; and that it prefers a non-accountable judiciary to make the rules by which it lives. This reasoning defies both common sense and accepted jurisprudential wisdom elsewhere. As American constitutional scholar Michael S. Paulsen put it: “So long as the courts wield enormous power, it is implausible, as well as wrong in principle, to insist that the people develop an attitude of respectful indifference to how and by whom that power is exercised.”52
VI
The expanding role of
The objection will undoubtedly be raised that democratizing the appointment process will undermine the independence of judges, who may feel they somehow “owe” something to those who placed them in power. Indeed, it was on the basis of this argument that the current system was introduced in the first place.55 Yet this argument demonstrates a misunderstanding of the basic workings of politics. Any judge whose salary and position are guaranteed for life is, almost by definition, impervious to political pressures, regardless of how he attained his position. There is no reason why a judge who has nothing to lose would allow a sense of misguided “gratitude” to interfere with the task of proper judgment. Indeed, this point has been made repeatedly by legal scholars.56 It is worth noting that in America’s two hundred years of experience with a democratically controlled judicial appointments system, United States Supreme Court justices have frequently ruled along lines entirely different from what their backers during the nomination process expected.57 Moreover, there is a crucial distinction between party partisanship and ideological partisanship: Clearly, judges must not be selected because of their affiliation with a political party. However, ideological partisanship is a legitimate criterion of judicial selection, since, as we have seen, the judicial task necessarily involves ideological decisions—and the public has a right to have a voice concerning which ideologies are shaping these decisions.
As for the objection that the Israeli legislature is too mired in petty partisanship to choose justices for the Supreme Court, the answer is simple: If the Knesset is competent to serve as the people’s representatives in passing constitutional laws that will bind future majorities, it is unreasonable to argue that it is not competent to approve appointments to the body that will determine what the constitution means.
A reformed selection mechanism is not only necessary in order to preserve the prestige of an increasingly embattled Supreme Court. It would also play an important role in strengthening Israeli democracy generally. One of the most debilitating illnesses of any democracy is for people to feel that their input does not matter, that they have no real control over their government, and therefore no reason to take public issues seriously. The judicial selections system fosters just this weakness, by sending the message that the people’s elected representatives cannot be trusted with the most important decisions, and that the question of who will occupy the nation’s courtrooms must instead be decided by a closed committee.
A reformed judicial appointments procedure should by all means protect the independence of
Mordechai Haller is an attorney living in
Notes
1. Charles L. Black, “A Note on Senatorial Consideration of Supreme Court Nominees,” Yale Law Journal 79, 1970, p. 660.
2. See Hillel Neuer, “Aharon Barak’s Revolution,” Azure 3, Winter 1998, pp. 13-49, and Evelyn Gordon, “Is It Legitimate to Criticize the Supreme Court?” AZURE 3, Winter 1998, pp. 50-89.
3. For the purposes of this article, the term “lifetime tenure” is meant to include systems in which judges’ positions are guaranteed until the age of retirement (in
4. Archibald Cox, The Role of the Supreme Court in American Government (Oxford: Clarendon, 1976), p. 99. See also Jeffrey A. Segal and Harold J. Spaeth, The Supreme Court and the Attitudinal Model (Cambridge: Cambridge, 1993), p. 4: “Judges of necessity make law. Only those who believe in fairy tales deny this statement. Even so ... it [is] unsettling to admit to judicial policy making because we have surrounded judicial decisions with a panoply of myth, the essence of which avers that judges and their decisions are objective, impartial and dispassionate.”
5. Yitzhak Englard, “The Contribution of Judicial Decisions to Tort Law Developments,” Iyunei Mishpat 11, 1985-1986, pp. 76, 90; cited in Menachem Mautner, The Decline of Formalism and the Rise of Values in Israeli Law (Tel Aviv: Ma’aglei Da’at, 1993), pp. 46-47. [Hebrew]
6. Aharon Barak, “The Judge-Made Rule and Social Reality,” in Volume in Memory of Yoel Zusman, Supreme Court President (Jerusalem: Daf Hen, 1984), p. 93.
7. Black, “A Note,” pp. 657-658. He identifies “the loci classici” of his approach in the writings of Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., Felix Frankfurter and Learned Hand. See also Eugene Rostow: “We have all long since agreed that judges are men, not automatons.... Inevitably they bring different views to the court....” Eugene V. Rostow, The Sovereign Prerogative: The Supreme Court and the Quest for Law (New Haven: Yale, 1962), p. 123; and Michael Paulsen: “Ideology matters: Whether a judicial candidate is an originalist, a formalist, a pragmatist, or a judicial activist, her judicial philosophy (and, depending on the candidate’s judicial philosophy, her political philosophy and personal views) on important issues is central to how she will behave as a judge.” Michael Stokes Paulsen, “Straightening Out the Confirmation Mess,” Yale Law Journal 105:2, November 1995, pp. 549-580.
8. Segal and Spaeth, Attitudinal Model, p. 65.
9. Alexander Hamilton, James Madison, John Jay, The Federalist Papers (New York: Bantam Books, 1982), no. 78, pp. 392-399; John Arthur, Words that Bind: Judicial Review and the Grounds of Modern Constitutional Theory (Boulder: Westview Press, 1995), passim.
10. Arthur, Words that Bind, pp. 1-3, 39, 132-133.
11. Federalist, no. 78. Equally important, judicial removal through the impeachment procedure was vested entirely in the legislative branch.
12. Herman Schwartz, Packing the Courts: The Conservative Campaign to Rewrite the Constitution (New York: Scribner, 1988), pp. 48-49.
13. Schwartz, Packing the Courts, p. 45. See also Henry J. Abraham, Justices and Presidents: A Political History of Appointments to the Supreme Court of the United States (New York: Oxford, 1974), pp. 33, 65. The first time the U.S. Senate rejected a nominee—whose name was submitted by President George Washington—was in 1795.
14. After being approved, Japanese judges serve life terms, subject to the review of the electorate every ten years. This is unusual among democracies, in that it places a relatively low premium on independence.
15. Conspicuously absent from the list is the United Kingdom, whose system of selecting justices is—as in so many other areas of British government—sui generis. The highest court is a committee of the House of Lords, an unelected and ostensibly legislative body which at the same time is supposed to embody the constitutional values of the nation, the way the supreme court does in other countries. The “Law Lords,” as the justices are called, are appointed by the queen upon recommendation by the prime minister, who in turn is advised by the Lord Chancellor as well as a number of sitting Law Lords and legal experts.
17. The full text of the relevant provisions reads: “Appointment of Judges: 4. (a) A judge shall be appointed by the President of the State upon election by a Judicial Selections Committee. (b) The Committee shall consist of nine members, namely, the President of the Supreme Court, two other judges of the Supreme Court elected by the body of judges thereof, the Minister of Justice and another Minister designated by the Government, two members of the Knesset elected by the Knesset and two representatives of the Israel Bar elected by the National Council of the Bar. The Minister of Justice shall be the chairman of the Committee.”
18. Under the last government, Justice Minister Tzahi Hanegbi was so pusillanimous toward the justices that he effectively expanded the bloc to four, agreeing with every appointment proposed by the justices. When Barak spoke last June at a farewell party for Hanegbi, Barak praised him for “running the meetings honestly and effectively. In his positions he agreed with the proposals which the Supreme Court justices brought before the committee.” Ha’aretz, June 7, 1999.
19. Unless he is busy representing the interests of his own party. Under the Netanyahu government, the ministerial representative on the committee was Education Minister Yitzhak Levy of the National Religious Party. His most pressing concern, it would appear, was increasing the number of Orthodox Supreme Court justices. See, for example, Ha’aretz, October 23, 1996. It is fair to assume that whenever the government’s minister is not a member of the dominant coalition party, his sectoral interests will come into play as well.
20. There is another possibility: That the committee will become a battlefield for the personal grudges between the lawyers and the justices. In a tense meeting of the five legal-establishment members of the committee in November 1996 to discuss upcoming judicial appointments, the former chairman of the Israel Bar Association, Dror Hoter-Yishai, accused the judges of “taking revenge” against him for his involvement in a number of cases which had come before them. Kol Ha’ir, December 6, 1996. Recently, a campaign has been waged to have Hoter-Yishai removed from his position on the committee. Ha’aretz, May 4, 1999.
21. Ha’aretz, December 13, 1993.
22. See Ha’aretz, November 13, 1995. Regarding the personal relationship between the Barak and Beinish families, see Kol Ha’ir, November 17, 1995.
23. See Kol Ha’ir, June 14, 1996.
24. There are a number of distinctions between the role of president of the Supreme Court in
25. Globes, July 16, 1997. To Transportation Minister Yitzhak Levy of the National Religious Party, Barak promised the nomination of an additional Orthodox justice; to MK Amnon Rubinstein of Meretz, Barak promised the nomination of an Arab justice.
26. Martin Edelman, Courts, Politics and Culture in
27. Yitzhak Olshan, Law and Words (Jerusalem: Shocken, 1978), p. 247. [Hebrew]
28. Moshe Ben-Ze’ev, “Politics in the Appointment of Judges,” Orech Hadin, May 27, 1981, p. 13.
29. Article 1(c), Courts Ordinance (Transitional Provisions) no. 11, 5708.
30. Elyakim Rubinstein, Judges of the Land: The Origin and Character of the
31. Smoira and Rosen were aware of the real or apparent conflict of interest; Smoira asked Rosen to obscure his role in the appointment. Rubinstein, Judges of the Land, p. 60.
32. Rubinstein, Judges of the Land, pp. 60-66.
33. Knesset Proceedings, vol. 8 (1951), p. 1176, cited in Rubinstein, Judges of the Land, pp. 105-106.
34. Rubinstein, Judges of the Land, p. 106.
35. Olshan, Law and Words, p. 328. Justice Olshan’s memoirs depict a deep antagonism to religious Jews, and refer repeatedly to Orthodox “conspiracies” to impose religious law on the Israeli public. See, for example, p. 327, and chapter 31, passim. In Rubinstein’s words, “His book is permeated, to a great degree, with harsh criticism (out of respect I do not use a sharper term) of Israeli religious circles….” Rubinstein, Judges of the Land, pp. 154-155.
36. Ha’aretz, August 24, 1978, cited in Rubinstein, Judges of the Land, p. 120.
37. Ha’aretz, October 23, 1996.
38. Ze’ev Segal, “A Constitution without a Constitution: The Israeli Experience and the American Impact,”
39. Rubinstein, Judges of the Land, p. 119.
40. For a general discussion on the ethnic and religious makeup of the courts, see Rubinstein, Judges of the Land, pp. 137-157. See also Shimon Shetreet, Justice in
41. Rubinstein, Judges of the Land, pp. 36-37; Supreme Court Public Relations Office; Yo’av Yitzhak, First Class: 1998 (Tel Aviv: Egel Hazahav, 1998), pp. 55-73. [Hebrew]
42. Based on information conveyed by the Supreme Court Public Relations Office; see also Yitzhak, First Class, pp. 55-73.
43. Rubinstein, Judges of the Land, p. 218. Further, “in light of the advanced age of most of the justices, their compulsory lack of contact with the community and their immersion in a judicial tradition whose aim is to distance judges from external pressures, their outlook is liable to be different than that of the general public.” Shimon Shetreet, “Reflections on the Protection of the Right of the Individual: Form and Substance,” Israel Law Review 12, 1977, p. 32, cited in Rubinstein, Judges of the Land, p. 218.
44. Rostow was referring more generally to the task of constitutional adjudication. Rostow, Sovereign, p. 93. See also Rubinstein, Judges of the Land, p.
45. Aharon Barak, “The Constitutional Revolution: Protected Human Rights,” Mishpat Umimshal 1, 1992-1993, p. 30, cited in Neuer, “Aharon Barak’s Revolution,” pp. 47-48.
46. Aharon Barak, Judicial Discretion, trans. Yadin Kaufmann (New Haven: Yale, 1989), pp. 36-41; Barak, Interpretation in Law (Jerusalem: Nevo, 1992), pp. 231, 345; Aharon Barak, “Basic Law: Freedom of Occupation,” Mishpat Umimshal 2, 1994, p. 208, cited in Neuer, “Aharon Barak’s Revolution,” p. 46, note 62.
47. Barak, “Freedom of Occupation,” p. 208, cited in Neuer, “Aharon Barak’s Revolution,” p. 32.
48. Moshe Landau, quoted in Ben-Dror Yemini, “Enlightened Fundamentalism,” Ha’aretz, October 1, 1997, p. 28.
49. Yemini, “Fundamentalism,” p. 28.
50. Cox, Role of the Supreme Court, pp. 117-118. Furthermore: “The power of the Supreme Court to command acceptance and support for its role in government seems to depend upon a sufficiently widespread conviction that it is acting legitimately, that is, performing the functions assigned to it, and only those functions, in the manner assigned.” Cox, Role of the Supreme Court, pp. 104-105. Rostow concurs, “For the people, and not the courts, are the final interpreters of the Constitution. The Supreme Court and the Constitution it expounds cannot survive unless the people are willing, by and large, to live under it.” Rostow, Sovereign, p. 142.
51. Segal, “A Constitution,” p. 16. Rubinstein agrees with Segal’s characterization that the present judicial selections system “is an attempt to neutralize appointments from politicization.” Rubinstein, Judges of the Land, p. 115.
52. Paulsen, “Straightening Out,” p. 579.
53. See Paulsen: “The prospect of open, substantive ideological review of judicial candidates always raises [the] objection ... that it would require a judge to commit herself to voting certain ways in cases that may come before her, compromising both judicial independence and judicial ethics ... [but] serious pre-appointment discussion of judicial philosophy simply does not compromise the constitutional independence of life-tenured judges, once they have been confirmed and appointed.” Paulsen continues: “The political branches may demand information necessary to enable them to make informed predictions, but they may not extract promises or pledges. A nominee may answer any and all substantive questions, but always with the reservation of the right to change her mind and always with the caveat that, though she has preliminary views, any particular case must be decided on the basis of its facts and in light of the legal arguments presented.” Paulsen, “Straightening Out,” pp. 570-573. See also Alexander Hamilton: “As nothing can contribute so much to [the judiciary’s] firmness and independence as permanency in office, this quality may therefore be justly regarded as an indispensable ingredient in its constitution....” Federalist, no. 78; and Shetreet: “The rules regarding the tenure of judges generally lie at the foundation of an independent judicial system.” Shetreet, Justice in
p. 54.
54. “Judges who never have to seek or preserve electoral support have no incentive to please supporters, or to consider how their decisions, particularly in high-profile cases, will be received by the citizenry.” Steven P. Croley, “The Majoritarian Difficulty: Elective Judiciaries and the Rule of Law,” The
55. Knesset Proceedings, vol. 8 (1951), pp. 1176-1179, 1191-1192; Knesset Proceedings, vol. 13 (1953), pp. 440-442. See also Olshan, Law and Words, p. 224; Rubinstein, Judges of the Land, pp. 103-120; Asher Arian, Politics in Israel: The Second Generation (Chatham: Chatham House, 1985), p. 182.
56. Croley, “The Majoritarian Difficulty,” pp. 746-747.
57. Far from viewing the courts as a threat, the framers of the U.S. Constitution “were more concerned lest the judges become subservient to either of the other branches. To insure the judiciary’s independence, the framers provided them with lifetime tenure, no reduction in salary, and created a selection process that neither the President nor the Congress could control.” Segal and Spaeth, Attitudinal Model, p. 13.